Which one of the following most accurately expresses the main conclusion of the argument?

This is a Main Conclusion question.

This is a tough problem that requires you to be good at (1) conditional logic – including how to handle the less common indicator “except,” (2) distinguishing context from argument, (3) tracking when one term is used interchangeably with another, and (4) managing abstract concepts – either by bringing the concepts down to earth using your own examples, or by mentally stuffing those concepts into a box to stop them from distracting you. Let’s throw in this skill, too: (5) strategic skimming.

Ready to dig in? Note that I’ll start with an explanation from the perspective of someone who is strong at the skills this problem is testing, but not quite an LSAT demigod. Extra comments that flesh things out a bit more will follow at the end.

We start with the following: The end of an action is the intended outcome of the action and not a mere by-product of the action…

What?

Let’s make sure to stop and translate that into something that makes sense. Resist the urge to immediately skim for the conclusion and hope that that will be enough to solve the question. The LSAT often doesn’t make the conclusion too difficult to find – but the challenge is in actually understanding what it’s saying and being ready for the correct answer to phrase that idea in different ways, including ways that require you to understand other parts of the stimulus. Don’t get me wrong – as I alluded to above, strategic skimming is an important skill, and one we will use. But try your best to understand the first line, in both LR and RC, even if it means slowing down, re-reading, and breaking down a statement into its separate parts.

The end of an action is the intended outcome of an action – this refers to the purpose of an action. You go to the gym to get healthier. You set an alarm in the morning to get up early for a flight. What you hope to achieve by doing something is the “end” of the action.

The stimulus contrasts the purpose of the action with “a mere by-product of the action.” You can tell there’s a contrast because the statement defines an “end” by defining what it is and what it’s not. “By-product” is an important word to know on the LSAT, since it comes up in other questions. But even if you don’t know exactly what it means, you can tell that it is not an intended outcome.

You go to the gym to get healthier, but a by-product of going to the gym is feeling insecure. You set an alarm in the morning to get up early for a flight, but a by-product of setting an alarm is feeling tired when you wake up.

(The distinction this problem makes between intended outcomes and unintended outcomes recurs all over the place in LSAT LR. You would do well to remember that whatever someone intends by doing an action can be completely different from the actual consequences of the action.)

So we know what the end of an action is – the outcome you want from it.

The first sentence finishes: …and the end’s value is thus the only reason for the action.

What?

How does that follow from the first half of the statement? Honestly even I’m lost at this point – lost in terms of the content. But the structure is clear from the word “thus.” That means this part of the sentence – that an end’s value is the only reason for the action – is a conclusion supported by the first half of the sentence. How does the definition of an end tell us what its value is? And is “the only reason for the action” supposed to be the same as the “intended outcome”? Let’s set these questions aside, because we may not need to resolve them in order to get the question correct.

So far, we have a premise, followed by a conclusion all in the first sentence. Let’s keep reading.

So while it is true that – let’s stop right here.

The next sentence begins with the word “So” – this means that we’re about to get a conclusion. And it would be the main conclusion of the argument, because it’s following from – or in other words, being supported by – the previous sentence, which contained a premise-conclusion structure.

However, immediately after “So” we get the phrase “while it is true…”. That phrase is a classic indicator of a concession – something the author of the argument acknowledges might be true, but does not play any supporting role in the argument. You can often strategically skim through a concession, without needing to fully digest it, if your goal is simply to identify and understand the main conclusion.

That means we’re about to get something that’s not the conclusion. Let’s skim this part:

… while it is true that not every end’s value will justify any means, and even, perhaps, that there is no end whose value will justify every means, …

The structure “while it is true that [X] and that [Y]” tells us that both X and Y are part of the concession, because “it” is a reference to both X and Y. What are the things that are true? X and Y. You can rephrase this as “while X is true and Y is true…”.

Finally, we get to the main conclusion:

… it is clear that nothing will justify a means except an end’s value.

I was hoping this would make more sense by now. All that work understanding the first part of the first sentence hasn’t really paid off. At least we know that that statement is the main conclusion, because the first sentence has a premise-conclusion structure, and, once we cut out the concession, the word “So” and the phrase “it is clear that” tells us that the last part follows from the first sentence.

So we’re looking for an answer that best matches the meaning of “...nothing will justify a means except an end’s value.”

What does that mean? I’m not sure what a “means” is…nor what the “end’s value” is exactly. But I do know what “except” means. It introduces an exception, which you can handle like the word “unless.”. So let’s take one half of the statement and make it the sufficient condition, but negated. I’ll pick “end’s value.”

If something is NOT an end’s value → then it cannot justify a means.

The contrapositive, which we can get by switching both sides of the arrow and negating, looks like this:

If something will justify a means → the thing must be an end’s value.

Both this version of the conditional and the original version are expressing the idea that being an end’s value is necessary in order to justify a means.

That’s the main conclusion. We can understand the structure of it pretty well, and the content less well, but I’m still confident we can get to the correct answer. One thing before we move to the answers: Do not, for any reason, confuse sufficiency with necessity. An end’s value is necessary for justifying a means. But that doesn’t mean that an end’s value is enough by itself to justify a means.

Answer Choice (A) The value of some ends may justify any means.

This isn’t saying that an end’s value is necessary for something else. It’s saying that an end’s value might do something else.

Answer Choice (B) One can always justify a given action by appeal to the value of its intended outcome.

This answer tells us that you can always justify an action by appealing to value. But that’s not what the conclusion said. It said that appealing to value is needed for justification…that doesn’t mean that in all circumstances, it can always justify another thing.

If that explanation doesn’t click, we can break it down a bit more. What is the sufficient condition of this answer choice? What’s the part that, if you do it, leads to an outcome? Here, it’s “appealing to value.” If you do that, you can always justify.

Another way to get to that understanding is through the word “always.” You can think of “always” as indicating necessity. If something always happens, it must happen.

“The trains to Philadelphia are always late.” That means if something is a train to Philly, then it must be late.

“It’s always raining during the winter in Seattle.” What’s the thing that’s always happening? Raining. So that is what’s necessary: If it’s winter in Seattle, then it must be raining.

This answer choice tells us that “justify” is necessary (the right side of the arrow), when the main conclusion had “justify” as sufficient (the left side of the arrow). This alone tells us it’s wrong.

Correct Answer Choice (C) One can justify an action only by appeal to the value of its intended outcome.

This is the conditional structure we were looking for. “Only by” introduces what’s necessary. So this is saying that appealing to value is necessary for justifying an action. In other words:

Justify action → Appeal to value of the action’s intended outcome

(“Appeal” in this context means to use or rely on – it’s a word we definitely need to understand for the LSAT.)

Now we shouldn’t be immediately comfortable picking this answer, since we haven’t confirmed that “end’s value” and “value of the action’s intended outcome” are the same concept, or that justifying an “action” is the same as justifying a “means.” In a timed situation, we’d want to get rid of the other answers and select this by process of elimination.

See the extra commentary after answer choice (E) for a full account of why this answer choice is correct.

Answer Choice (D) Only the value of the by-products of an action can justify that action.

The value of the by-products? Because we took time to understand the meaning of “by-products” earlier, it’s easier to see that the stimulus never talked about the value of by-products. So this is certainly not the main conclusion.

Answer Choice (E) Nothing can justify the intended outcome of an action except the value of that action’s actual outcomes.

This answer refers to the “actual outcomes” of an action. That phrase was never used – could it refer to “by-products” (the unintended outcomes of an action)? Maybe. But we can still eliminate this answer, since the value of either actual outcomes or by-products isn’t what the conclusion refers to. We are looking for something about the value of intended outcomes.

(E) got close though. With some edits, we can make it right: Nothing can justify an action except the value of that action’s intended outcomes.

The original version of (E) claimed that good intentions don’t matter unless the actual outcomes are good. Let that sink in. It’s a commonly held belief. Another way to put it is to let the results be the judge. That’s very different from the modified version of (E) which claims that it’s only the good intentions that matter. Nothing else can justify an action. Only the intentions matter.

Answer Choice (C), continued:

So you want to know why the conclusion’s reference to “end’s value” and “justify a means” matches (C)'s use of “value of its intended outcome” and “justify an action”? Keep reading.

Look back to the first part of the first sentence.

The end of an action is the intended outcome of the action…

We know that the “end” of an action is the intended outcome. So when the conclusion refers to an “end’s value” – we can replace the word “end” with its definition: “intended outcome’s value.” That’s why “value of its intended outcome” matches in (C). Remember what we just did here – the LSAT will commonly spike a problem’s difficulty by requiring us to replace a word with how the stimulus defined that word.

Next, to figure out why “action” is the same as “means,” perhaps we can think about the definition of “action” and “means” and see that they are similar? The means is a way of doing something – so it can encompass the actions you take in order to do something. I’m comfortable with this understanding in a timed situation, particularly if we eliminated the other answers.

A slightly more solid reason that “action” and “means” are interchangeable is tied to the stimulus. Let’s go back to the second half of the first sentence:

… and the end’s value is thus the only reason for the action.

The word “reason” was ambiguous to me when we first discussed it earlier in this explanation – it seemed initially as if it could mean “purpose” – the reason you go to the dentist is your purpose for going to the dentist (cleaner teeth), for example.

But “reason” can also mean justification. Using that meaning, this statement is saying “the intended outcome’s value is the only justification for the action.” For example, if we use the examples at the beginning of the explanation: the value of getting healthier is the only justification for going to the gym. And the value of waking up early to get on a flight is the only justification for setting an alarm.

Immediately after that line, the stimulus launches into the concession – “while it is true that not every end’s value will justify any means…”. Why would the author talk about this?

I think this is why. The previous sentence just said that an end’s value is the only justification (reason) for the action. This means that if an action can be justified, that justification must be the end’s value. The author now wants to clarify the limits of what she just said.

“I’m not saying that every intended outcome will justify any action that produces that outcome – you can’t drop a nuclear bomb on your neighbor to stop him from playing loud music. And I’m also not saying that there’s some holy, amazing, perfect, humanitarian outcome that will justify every action that produces that outcome – no matter how great world peace would be, that would not justify sacrificing a child to a god who demands blood in exchange for granting world peace.”

If we understand that this is what the author is doing, it’s much easier to see that her transition to using the word “means” doesn’t change what she’s talking about. She’s still talking about the “actions” in the first sentence. So the conclusion’s use of “justify a means” is equivalent to “justify an action” in (C).


272 comments

The main conclusion drawn in Helen's argument is that

We’re looking for the Main Conclusion of Helen’s argument.

Helen is the morally upstanding sibling in her family. She begins her argument:

It was wrong of my brother Mark to tell our mother that... blah blah blah

Don’t just keep reading the super long sentence. Stop to register 3 things: (1) We’re about to get what Mark told his mom, (2) Helen says Mark was wrong to tell their mom what he told her, (3) there is a high chance that the value judgment that Mark was “wrong” is the conclusion.

Now let’s keep reading.

...the reason he had missed her birthday party the evening before was that he had been in a traffic accident and that by the time he was released from the hospital emergency room the party was long over.

Apparently, Mark missed their mom’s birthday party and told her that it was because he got into a traffic accident. Helen says Mark was wrong to tell their mom that. Why was it wrong?

Saying something that is false can never be other than morally wrong, and there had been no such accident – Mark had simply forgotten all about the party.

In this line, Helen does two things. First, she gives us a moral rule she’s using regarding what’s wrong – saying something false is wrong. Second, she gives us the fact that shows what Mark said was false. He just forgot about their mom’s party – there was no accident.

That makes sense – Mark said something false, and saying something false is wrong. Thus, the conclusion of the argument is what we were thinking from the first sentence: Mark was wrong to tell their mom what he told her.

Answer Choice (A) Mark did not tell his mother the truth

This is supported by the stimulus, but it’s not the conclusion. The conclusion is Helen’s judgment about what Mark said. If you think that (A) is the conclusion, ask yourself what the role is played by the claim that Mark was wrong. It would seem to have no place in your conception of the argument. That should cause you to ask whether you have the right framing.

Answer Choice (B) the real reason Mark missed his mother’s birthday party was that he had forgotten all about it

This is a true statement – it comes from the last part of the last sentence. But this is not the conclusion. Helen doesn’t give us another statement that is supposed to prove that he had forgotten about the party. She simply states as a fact that he forgot. That means it’s not a conclusion.

Answer Choice (C) it is wrong to attempt to avoid blame for one’s failure to do something by claiming that one was prevented from doing that thing by events outside one’s control

This starts off OK, but the thing (C) is calling wrong isn’t what we were looking for. Helen’s conclusion was about a specific situation - what Mark said. This answer is about the more general idea of avoiding blame for failure to do something based on events outside one’s control. That’s not the specific situation Helen was talking about.

Correct Answer Choice (D) it was wrong of Mark to tell his mother that he had missed her birthday party as a result of having been in a traffic accident

This is a restatement of the first sentence. It leaves out some of the details (such as the fact Mark said he went to the hospital emergency room), but that’s OK, since those details weren’t important. The point of what Mark said was that he couldn’t make it to the birthday party; Helen’s conclusion is that what Mark said was wrong.

Answer Choice (E) it is always wrong not to tell the truth

This is supported by the beginning part of the last sentence. But that was offered as support for the conclusion in the first sentence.

If you thought (E) was the conclusion, you are either confused about your task or about the structure of the stimulus. Our task is to identify the conclusion that the author actually gave us, not simply to pick an answer the author agrees with.

If you were confused about the structure of the stimulus, and thought that the line beginning with “Saying something that is false can never be…” was the conclusion, then you should get into the habit of asking, “Why should I believe that?” For anything you think is the conclusion, you should be able to point to a statement that is offered as support. Here, Helen doesn’t give us anything to help prove that it’s wrong to say something false. She simply states that as a moral principle, without justifying why we should follow it. That means it’s not the conclusion.


105 comments

Mayor of Outerville, a suburb of Center City: Outerville must grow if it is to survive, so, as we have agreed, efforts should be made to attract more residents. The best strategy for attracting residents is to renovate the train station. The numbers of jobs in Center City and of people who prefer to live in suburban towns are increasing. With the rise in tolls, driving into the city is becoming more expensive than train travel. Therefore, people want to live in towns where train travel is convenient and pleasant.

Summary

Outerville is a suburb of Center City. If Outerville survives, it must grow. Outerville should make efforts to attract more residents. The best strategy to attract new residents is to renovate the train station. The number of jobs in Center City is increasing. The number of people who want to live in suburbs is increasing. Tolls are rising, causing driving to the city to become more expensive than traveling by train. People want to live in areas with convenient and pleasant train travel.

Strongly Supported Conclusions

If Outerville renovates the train station, it will make train travel more convenient and pleasant, attracting people who want to live in the suburb but commute by train to Center City’s jobs.

A
the town of Outerville should attract more residents

This is unsupported because this information is already presented as a premise to the argument. We already know that the town should attract more residents, but this points to a separate conclusion.

B
the train station in Outerville should be renovated

This is strongly supported because the mayor states that the best strategy for attracting new residents to Outerville is to renovate the train station.

C
residents of Outerville who are in need of work should look for jobs in Center City

This is unsupported because the mayor doesn’t make any value statement on where people should look for work. They mayor’s value statement is limited to saying what the best strategy is for Outerville to attract new residents.

D
people who work in Center City but live in Outerville should commute by train rather than driving

This is unsupported because although people who work in Center City but live in Outerville may prefer to commute by train, the mayor makes no prescriptive statement saying these people should commute by train.

E
people who want to live where train travel is convenient and pleasant should live in Outerville

This is unsupported because we don’t have any statement declaring where people should or should not live.

</section


133 comments

Lack of exercise produces the same or similar bodily effects as aging. In fact, the physical changes that accompany aging can often be slowed down by appropriate exercise. No drug, however, holds any promise for slowing down the changes associated with aging. Therefore, _______.

Summary
Aging and lack of exercise cause similar effects on the body. Physical changes that accompany aging can be slowed by exercise. However, no drug is promising when it comes to slowing physical changes accompanying aging.

Strongly Supported Conclusions
Exercise is more reliable than drugs when it comes to slowing down the physical changes that accompany age.

A
taking drugs has the same effect on aging as does a lack of exercise
This answer is unsupported. We don’t know whether taking drugs causes similar physical changes to the body compared to lack of exercise.
B
people who do not exercise are likely to need drugs to sustain their health
This answer is unsupported. We don’t know whether people who do not exercise need drugs to sustain their health. We only know that lack of exercise contributes to bodily changes in a similar way that aging does.
C
appropriate exercise can prevent the physical changes associated with aging
This answer is unsupported. We don’t know whether exercise prevents physical changes. Rather, we only know that exercise slows these physical changes.
D
people who do not exercise when they are young will gain few benefits from beginning to exercise at a later age
This answer is unsupported. We don’t know whether the beneficial effects of exercise are different at different ages.
E
if the physical changes of aging are to be slowed, it is more practical to rely on exercise than on drugs
This answer is strongly supported. Since drugs do not hold any promise for slowing down physical changes associated with aging, it’s better to rely on exercise to slow these changes.

22 comments